Conversion of Consciousness as Principle of Morality
DOI:
https://doi.org/10.15448/1984-6746.2016.3.21114Keywords:
Aristotle. Friendship. Kant. Normativity. Morality.Abstract
Kant shows that a fundamental theory of normativity and morality can give neither an explanation nor an explication of normativity, but can only articulate and render explicit its origin. It can do so by indicating the place or topos and the turn or trope of its originating. According to Kant, the topos of normativity is the will qua practical reason and its trope is the general, typically instrumental use of this reason, i.e. reflection. The trope of the origin of morality is autonomy, i.e. practical reason turning on itself and thus becoming pure practical reason, thereby establishing its own form as law: the categorical imperative. Consequently, fundamental ethics serves two functions (if it is indeed successful): formally, it provides evidence for the originality or authenticity of morality; materially, it gives a criteriological principle for the content of morality. The article argues that Kant was right in his view of the foundation of ethics, but was wrong in the manner in which he met the requirements thus established. The topos of normativity and, consequently, of morality cannot be reason, but must be consciousness or, more precisely, (actual) knowledge de se; and its fundamental trope cannot be reflection (and then autonomy), but must be what can be described as a conversion of consciousness. This conversion can be identified with philein in the sense of Aristotle. It has four different aspects: desire, cognition, benevolence, and recognition. When philein is reciprocal and lived, philia ensues. Friendship (in the broad sense of Aristotle) is then described as the topos of the origin of Normativity and Morality.
Downloads
References
CASTAÑEDA, Hector-Neri. 'He': A study in the logic of self-consciousness. In: BROOK, Andrew; DeVIDI Richard C. (Eds.). Self-reference and Self-awareness. Amsterdam; Philadelphia: John Bejamins Publishing Company, 2001. p. 51-80. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1075/aicr.30.07cas
COOPER, John. "Aristotle on the Forms of Friendship". Review of Metaphysics, 30 (1976), p. 619-648. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/oseo/instance.00258586
FRANK, Manfred. Ansichten der Subjektivität. Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp, 2012.
KANT, Immanuel. Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten [1785]. In: ______.
Gesammelte Schriften. Berlin: Königlich Preußische Akademie der Wissenschaften, 1911. v. 4, p. 385-463.
KANT, Immanuel. Kritik der praktischen Vernunft [1788]. In: ______. Gesammelte Schriften. Berlin: Königlich Preußische Akademie der Wissenschaften, 1913. v. 5, p. 1-163.
LABERGE, Pierre. La définition de la volonté comme faculté d’agir selon la représentation des lois (GMS 412). In: HÖFFE, Ottfried. Kants Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten: Ein kooperativer Kommentar. 4. ed. Frankfurt a.M.: Klostermann, 2010. p. 83-96.
MOORE, George Edward. Principia Etica. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1903.
SOLOKOWSKI, Robert. Phénoménologie de l’amitié. In: MERLE, J.-C.; SCHUMACHER, B.N. (Eds.). L’amitié. Paris, 2006. p. 115-135.
STEIGLEDER, Klaus. Kants Moralphilosophie: Die Selbstbezüglichkeit reiner praktischer Vernunft.Stuttgart. Weimar: Metzler, 2002. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-476-02850-1
UTZ, Konrad. Freundschaft. Eine philosophische Theorie. Paderborn: Schöningh, 2012. DOI: https://doi.org/10.30965/9783657773985
UTZ, Konrad. Bewusstsein. Eine philosophische Theorie. Paderborn: Schöningh, 2015. DOI: https://doi.org/10.30965/9783657781232
UTZ, Konrad. "Praktische Vernunft in der 'Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten'". Zeitschrift für philosophische Forschung, 69, 4 (2015), p. 474-501. DOI: https://doi.org/10.3196/004433015816987885
UTZ, Konrad. "Quid mihi? Zur Methode der Grundlegung der Ethik bei Kant". Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie, 64, 2 (2016), p. 213-227. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/dzph-2016-0015
Downloads
Published
How to Cite
Issue
Section
License
Copyright
The submission of originals to Revista Veritas implies the transfer by the authors of the right for publication. Authors retain copyright and grant the journal right of first publication. If the authors wish to include the same data into another publication, they must cite Revista Veritas as the site of original publication.
Creative Commons License
Except where otherwise specified, material published in this journal is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International license, which allows unrestricted use, distribution and reproduction in any medium, provided the original publication is correctly cited. Copyright: © 2006-2020 EDIPUCRS</p